
| |
Broadcasts
Celia Heyes on Cognitive Gadgets.
Social Science Bites, June2018
Cognitive Gadgets.
Interview by Russell Gray, Director of the Max Planck Institute for the
Science of Human History, Jena, Germany, November 2018
The Evolution of Cognition. The Measure of
Everyday Life, US public radio, March 2019
The Chandaria Lectures
For a general
audience:
Lecture 1
Cognitive Gadgets
Lecture 2
Gadgets for Mindreading and Imitation
Lecture 3
Cultural Evolutionary Psychology
Evolutionary psychology casts the human mind as a collection of cognitive
instincts - organs of thought shaped by genetic evolution and constrained
by the needs of our Stone Age ancestors. This picture was plausible 25
years ago but, I argue, it no longer fits the facts. Research involving
infants and nonhuman animals now suggests that genetic evolution has
merely tweaked the human mind, making us more friendly than our pre-human
ancestors, more attentive to other agents, and giving us souped-up,
general-purpose mechanisms of learning, memory and control. Using these
resources, our special-purpose organs of thought are built in the course
of development through social interaction. They are products of cultural
rather than genetic evolution; cognitive gadgets rather than cognitive
instincts.
Chandaria Lectures, Institute of Philosophy, Senate House, University of
London, 8-15 December 2017. |
 |
On human irrationality
(audio file of interview)
Interview with Stig Abell, editor of the Times Literary Supplement,
on 'The Enigma of Reason' by Hugo Mercier and Dan Sperber. Released
on 26 July, 2017. The segment starts at 18:00 minures.
Heyes, C. M. (2017)
From deflection to despair
Review
of ‘The Enigma of Reason’ by Hugo Mercier and Dan Sperber. The Times
Literary Supplement, 28 July.
|

|
The cultural evolution
of mind reading
(audio
file
of interview)
Abstract: It is not just a manner of
speaking: “Mind reading,” or working out what others are thinking and
feeling, is markedly similar to print reading. Both of these distinctly
human skills recover meaning from signs, depend on dedicated cortical
areas, are subject to genetically heritable disorders, show cultural
variation around a universal core, and regulate how people behave. But
when it comes to development, the evidence is conflicting. Some studies
show that, like learning to read print, learning to read minds is a long,
hard process that depends on tuition. Others indicate that even very
young, nonliterate infants are already capable of mind reading. Here, we
propose a resolution to this conflict. We suggest that infants are
equipped with neurocognitive mechanisms that yield accurate expectations
about behaviour (“automatic” or “implicit” mind reading), whereas
“explicit” mind reading, like literacy, is a culturally inherited skill;
it is passed from one generation to the next by verbal instruction.
Heyes,
C. M. & Frith, C.
(2014)
The cultural evolution of mind reading.
Science,
344,
1243091. DOI: 10.1126/science.1243091. |
  |
On the origins of
mindreading (video
file of talk for a specialist audience)
Abstract: Many philosophers and
psychologists believe that the capacity to ‘read minds’ or ‘mentalise’
depends on dedicated cognitive processes—processes that operate in a
different way from those involved in other tasks—and that, in the course
of human evolution, natural selection has produced a highly specific,
genetically inherited predisposition to develop these dedicated
mindreading processes. This has been described as the nativist or
modular view of mindreading and contrasted with more developmental
or constructivist accounts, which emphasise the importance of the
individual’s experience, and especially their social experience, in the
development of mindreading. Nativist views tend to be representationalist
and built on laboratory-based experimental methods, whereas constructive
views tend to resist representationalism and to draw on more naturalistic
empirical methods. My recent work has crossed these traditions by
assuming that mindreading is representational; proposing that these
representations are products of cultural evolution; and challenging what
are normally regarded as the more rigorous empirical methods on their own
ground. This lecture will compare mindreading with print (or script)
reading, a capacity that emerged too recently in human history to be
dependent on genetically evolved cognitive processes. This comparison
helps to clear the ground for close examination of recent experiments that
have fortified nativist views by seeming to show that nonhuman primates,
infants, and adults are capable of automatic or implicit mindreading. It
also introduces the ‘softer’ but compelling evidence that the development
of mindreading is crucially dependent on linguistic communication between
adults and children.
Keynote lecture, European Society for
Philosophy and Psychology, organised by Daniel Cohnitz, Ian Phillips,
Hannes Rakoczy & Gillian Ramchand, University of Tartu, 14-17 July 2015.
Details of the meeting and podcasts of all invited talks at
http://espp2015.ut.ee/?page_id=9
|
 |
The cultural evolution of mind reading
(video
file of talk for a general audience)
How do
we know what's in other people's minds? How is this 'mindreading
ability' influenced by our cultural and evolutionary backgrounds?
When do we develop this skill?
Keynote lecture, Royal
Holloway, University of London. 27th January 2015 |
 |
Simple
minds: a qualified defence of associative learning
(audio
file)
(pdf)
Abstract:
Using cooperation in chimpanzees as a case study, this article argues that
research on animal minds needs to steer a course between
‘association-blindness’ – the failure to consider associative learning as a
candidate explanation for complex behaviour – and ‘simple-mindedness’ – the
assumption that associative explanations trump more cognitive hypotheses.
Association-blindness is challenged by the evidence that associative
learning occurs in a wide range of taxa and functional contexts, and is a
major force guiding the development of complex human behaviour.
Furthermore, contrary to a common view, association-blindness is not
entailed by the rejection of behaviourism. Simple-mindedness is founded on
Morgan’s canon, a methodological principle recommending ‘lower’ over
‘higher’ explanations for animal behaviour. Studies in the history and
philosophy of science show that Morgan failed to offer an adequate
justification for his canon, and subsequent attempts to justify the canon
using evolutionary arguments and appeals to simplicity have not been
successful. The weaknesses of association-blindness and simple-mindedness
imply that there are no short-cuts to finding out about animal minds. To
decide between associative and more cognitive explanations for animal
behaviour, we have to spell them out in sufficient detail to allow
differential predictions, and to test these predictions through observation
and experiment.
Royal Society Discussion Meeting, ‘Animal Minds: From Computation to
Evolution’, organised by Nicola Clayton, Uri Grodzinsky and Alex Thornton,
London, 16-17 January 2012. Details of the meeting and audio podcasts of
all talks at
http://royalsociety.org/events/2012/animal-minds-computation/
|
 |
Cultural inheritance of
cultural learning
(audio
file)
(video
file)
(pdf)
Abstract: Cumulative cultural evolution is what ‘makes us
odd’; our capacity to learn facts and techniques from others, and to refine
them over generations, plays a major role in making human minds and lives
radically different from those of other animals. In this article I discuss
cognitive processes that are known collectively as ‘cultural learning’
because they enable cumulative cultural evolution. These cognitive
processes include reading, social learning, imitation, teaching, social
motivation, and theory of mind. Taking the first of these three types of
cultural learning as examples, I ask whether and to what extent these
cognitive processes have been adapted genetically or culturally to enable
cumulative cultural evolution. I find that recent empirical work in
comparative psychology, developmental psychology and cognitive neuroscience
provides surprisingly little evidence of genetic adaptation, and ample
evidence of cultural adaptation. This raises the possibility that it is not
only ‘grist’ but also ‘mills’ that are culturally inherited; through social
interaction in the course of development, we not only acquire facts about
the world and how to deal with it (grist), we also build the cognitive
processes that make ‘fact inheritance’ possible (mills).
Workshop on ‘New Thinking: The Evolution of Human
Cognition’, funded by All Souls College, the British Academy, Guarantors of
Brain and Magdalen College, University of Oxford, June 2011. For details of the
meeting and audio/video podcasts of all talks click
here.
|
 |
What’s ‘social’ about social learning?
(audio
file)
(pdf)
Abstract: Research on social learning in animals has
revealed a rich variety of cases where animals - from caddis fly larvae to
chimpanzees – acquire biologically important information by observing the
actions of others. A great deal is known about the adaptive functions of
social learning, but very little about the cognitive mechanisms that make it
possible. Even in the case of imitation, a type of social learning studied
in both comparative psychology and cognitive science, there has been minimal
contact between the two disciplines. Social learning has been isolated from
cognitive science by two longstanding assumptions: that it depends on a set
of special-purpose modules – cognitive adaptations for social living; and
that these learning mechanisms are largely distinct from the processes
mediating human social cognition. Recent research challenges these
assumptions by showing that social learning co-varies with asocial learning;
occurs in solitary animals; and exhibits the same features in diverse
species, including humans. Drawing on this evidence, I argue that social
and asocial learning depend on the same basic learning mechanisms; these are
adapted for the detection of predictive relationships in all natural
domains; and they are associative mechanisms – processes that encode
information for long-term storage by forging excitatory and inhibitory links
between event representations. Thus, human and nonhuman social learning are
continuous, and social learning is adaptively specialised – it becomes
distinctively ‘social’ – only when input mechanisms (perceptual, attentional
and motivational processes) are phylogenetically or ontogenetically tuned to
other agents.
Royal Society Satellite Meeting, ‘Social Learning in Human and Nonhuman
Animals: Theoretical and Empirical Dissections’, organised by Andrew Whiten,
Kavli Royal Society International Centre, Buckinghamshire, 1-2 July 2010.
Details of the meeting and audio podcasts of all talks at
http://royalsociety.org/events/2010/social-learning/
|
 |
|