I. Authority and legitimacy
The state consists in a bunch of people following rules, some of which purport to entitle some of the people to tell the others what they may and may not do, and to physically force them to comply if necessary. How can that be morally acceptable? How can anyone gain the right to order others around like that? This week's topic takes this question as its starting point and considers possible responses to it.
Question: What, if anything, gives the state authority to impose its law?
Priority reading (Hide)
- Extracts from work by the great social contract theorists of the 17th and 18th centuries
The seven pages linked here include extracts from work by Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, and Kant, whose arguments continue to set the terms for thinking about political legitimacy today. The extracts are too short to give you a full picture, but they do give you a sense of the kind of argument each makes, and of some of the differences between them. (Do follow up by reading more from any that seems intriguing to you.) Many of the contemporary political philosophers represented below are social contract theorists inspired, directly or indirectly, by these texts.
- A. John Simmons, ‘Justification and Legitimacy’, in Justification and Legitimacy (Cambridge, 2000)
Simmons argues that justifying the state is not the same as legitimising its rule, issuing a challenge to contemporary political philosophers who have, in his view, blurred the distinction.
- Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Clarendon, 1986), chapters 2–4
Raz sets out his influential 'service conception' of justified authority and then applies it to the case of state authority. Raz's view is in part a direct response to the anarchist challenge from Wolff (see the further reading).
- Anna Stilz, Liberal Loyalty (Princeton, 2009), chapters 1–2
In these beautifully clear chapters, Stilz sets out a Kantian defence of state authority, casting Lockean anarchists such as A. John Simmons as her opponents.
- Jonathan Quong, Liberalism without Perfection (Oxford, 2010), chapter 4, sections 4.4–4.5 (pp. 126–35)
Quong offers a clear defence of the 'natural duty of justice' account of political authority, presenting it as a modification of Raz's account. Quong's account and Wellman's (see further reading) have some similarities, but they appear to yield very different conclusions about the scope of legitimate state action.
- Amanda Greene, ‘Legitimacy without Liberalism: A Defense of Max Weber’s Standard of Political Legitimacy’, Analyse & Kritik 39 (2017)
Greene defends a Weberian conception of political legitimacy as not merely a descriptive standard—as many political philosophers assume—but also a normative standard. The Weberian standard, she argues, has the virtue of being more clearly universally acceptable, more obviously a system-level property, and helpfully distinct from standards of justice. Greene’s ‘Is Political Legitimacy Worth Promoting?’ (Nomos 61 [2019]) usefully elaborates some of these claims further.)
- Rosalind Hursthouse, ‘After Hume’s Justice’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society vol. 91 (1990–1991)
Hursthouse takes inspiration from Hume in attacking the Lockean idea of a natural right as ‘naturally unintelligible’, making sense only as the child of convention. But this does not condemn us to thinking that justice and rights are whatever local laws say they are, she argues, for we can instead say that the explanatorily basic concept is that of a properly functioning society from which the standards for the conventions determining rights are derived.
- Niko Kolodny, ‘Political Rule and Its Discontents’, in Sobel, Vallentyne, and Wall (eds.), Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, Volume 2 (Oxford, 2016)
Kolodny argues that the presumption against state rule as a prima facie infringement of individual freedom, which drives a great deal of writing on state authority, is mistaken. Instead, he suggests, if there's any problem with relations of rule at all, has to do with worries about relations of equality.
Hide priority reading ⇑
Further reading (Hide)
- Amanda Greene, ‘Consent and Political Legitimacy’, in Sobel, Wall, and Vallentyne (eds.), Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, Volume 2 (Oxford, 2016)
Beginning from the idea that legitimacy requires the consent of the governed in some sense, Greene criticises both contractualist (here her target includes John Rawls and Rawlsians such as Quong) and voluntarist attempts to spell out conditions of legitimacy before presenting her own ‘sovereignty conception’, according to which a regime is legitimate insofar as it achieves “actual quality consent” to rule based on positive governance assessments. Greene argues that the sovereignty conception makes better sense of the value of legitimacy than its rivals.
- David Copp, ‘The Idea of a Legitimate State’, Philosophy & Public Affairs vol. 28, no. 1 (1999)
Copp argues for the authority of the state via the idea of 'societal basic needs', which are, he argues, best furthered by means of a system of law, whose effectiveness in turn calls for the moral powers associated with legitimacy.
- R.P. Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970), Part I
Wolff argues on Kantian grounds that authority relations are always objectionable. Aim to figure out which premisses are doing what work in his argument, and think about how plausible each is.
- Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Basic Books, 1974), Parts I–II
In Part I, Nozick tries to show (via an 'invisible hand' explanation) that a 'libertarian' minimal state could come into existence without violating the very strong rights of individual self-ownership that he defends. In Part II, he argues that anything more than the minimal state would violate individual rights and would, therefore, be illegitimate.
- David Schmidtz, ‘Justifying the State’, Ethics vol. 101, no. 1 (1990)
Schmidtz distinguishes and assesses a number of different methods of justifying the state that, he claims, are often conflated.
- Christopher Heath Wellman, ‘Toward a Liberal Theory of Political Obligation’, Ethics vol. 111, no. 4 (2001)
Wellman defends what he calls a 'samaritan' account of political legitimacy as a step towards his account of political obligation. The basic idea is that it's permissible to coerce some at reasonable cost in order to get them to save others from desperate peril, and that's what's going on in the case of (legitimate) state coercion. Since our interest this week is only in state authority, you can stop reading after p. 747.
- Arthur Isak Applbaum, ‘Legitimacy without the Duty to Obey’, Philosophy & Public Affairs vol. 38, no. 3 (2010)
Applbaum elaborates the interesting idea that legitimacy consists in a Hohfeldian moral power, not to impose moral duties to do as the law says, but to alter the normative standing of subjects in other ways—e.g. by altering the configuration of their Hohfeldian privileges and claims against each other.
Hide further reading ⇑
II. Equality
Something that many people take to be a plainly objectionable feature of contemporary political arrangements is the degree of inequality that they foster, both at the national and at the global level. But what exactly is wrong with inequality? Is any inequality between people objectionable? And is the objection to inequality of money, or of well-being, or of opportunity, or of something else? This week, we consider some of these questions, focusing primarily on the question what the best understanding of egalitarianism is, rather than whether we should be egalitarians at all. Some reading for the latter question is suggested in the further reading list below.
Question: How should we best understand the value of equality that underpins egalitarianism?
Priority reading (Hide)
- John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, revised edition (Harvard, 1999), sections 11–17
In these sections, Rawls argues for what he calls 'democratic equality', which comprises the 'difference principle' and the principle of 'fair equality of opportunity'. He defends democratic equality against some competing interpretations of the general idea that if there are to be any inequalities, they must work to everyone's advantage, which he takes to be justified by the contractualist approach. Rawls's arguments here have been hugely influential, as you’ll see.
- Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, Luck Egalitarianism (Bloomsbury, 2016), chapter 1
Lippert-Rasmussen summarises the core commitments of the luck egalitarian view and traces its development from some aspects of Rawls's argument via three of the philosophers most prominently associated with the view.
- Samuel Scheffler, ‘What is Egalitarianism’, Philosophy & Public Affairs vol. 31, no. 1 (2003)
Scheffler raises doubts about the importance and moral implications of the distinction between luck and choice that luck egalitarians place such weight upon, and sketches the relational egalitarian ideal as an alternative. He concludes with an analysis of Rawls's relationship to luck egalitarianism and some responses to objections. Scheffler elaborates these ideas further in ‘Choice, Circumstance, and the Value of Equality’ (Politics, Philosophy & Economics vol. 4, no. 1 [2005]) and ‘The Practice of Equality’, in Fourie, Schuppert, and Wallimann-Helmer (eds.), Social Equality (Oxford, 2015).
- Elizabeth Anderson, ‘The Fundamental Disagreement between Luck Egalitarians and Relational Egalitarians’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy supplementary volume 36 (2010)
Anderson, whose earlier paper ‘What is the Point of Equality?’ (see further reading) exploded mainstream thinking egalitarianism in Anglophone political philosophy, ties the relational egalitarian view of justice to contractualist ideas about interpersonal justification in ways that, according to her, make egalitarian evaluations of states of affairs derivative—in contrast to what she sees as the luck egalitarian approach.
- Zoltan Miklosi, ‘Varieties of Relational Egalitarianism’, in Sobel, Vallentyne, and Wall (eds.), Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, Volume 4
Miklosi surveys various conceptions of relational egalitarianism and asks whether they really entail a rejection of the ‘distributive’ approach to justice. He argues that most don't entail such a rejection, and that the only conceptions that do are implausible.
- Chiara Cordelli, ‘Justice as Fairness and Relational Resources’, The Journal of Political Philosophy vol. 23, no. 1 (2015)
Cordelli argues that certain interpersonal relationships, such as friendship, can be regarded as productive resources that are appropriately regarded as subject to principles of distributive justice. In this way, she seeks to show that distribution-focused conceptions of egalitarianism nevertheless offer reasons of justice for caring about how people relate to one another.
- Zofia Stemplowska, ‘Responsibility and Respect: Reconciling Two Egalitarian Visions’, in Knight and Stemplowska (eds.), Responsibility and Distributive Justice (Oxford, 2014)
Stemplowska reviews three different interpretations of luck egalitarianism's central idea, defending one that reads it as an articulation of the requirements of respect for others as moral equals. She goes on to argue that on this interpretation, there is no real conflict between luck egalitarianism and relational egalitarianism, and that luck egalitarianism is in one sense more fundamental.
Hide priority reading ⇑
Further reading (Hide)
- Serena Olsaretti, ‘Responsibility and the Consequences of Choice’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society vol. 109, part 2 (2009)
Olsaretti focuses on the key distinction between accepting choice-sensitivity and accepting what we might think of as the 'natural' consequences of choice.
- Elizabeth Anderson, ‘What is the Point of Equality?’, Ethics vol. 109, no. 2 (1999)
In this hugely influential article, Anderson attacks luck egalitarianism as a betrayal of egalitarian aims, and defends a version of what came to be known as relational egalitarianism instead. Addressing the objections she raises immediately became a necessary condition of a defensible luck egalitarianism.
- T. M. Scanlon, ‘The diversity of objections to inequality’, in his The Difficulty of Tolerance (Cambridge, 2003)
Scanlon surveys a number of different reasons for objecting to inequality, and offers some analysis of the ways in which these feature in Rawls's arguments. He ends with some reflections on the nature of one of the reasons he identifies, that it is an evil for people to be treated as or made to feel inferior.
- Zofia Stemplowska, ‘Making Justice Sensitive to Responsibility’, Political Studies vol. 57, no. 2 (2009)
Stemplowska defends the inclusion of responsibility-sensitivity in the standards of egalitarian justice against the critiques of relational egalitarians, pointing out that luck egalitarians can advocate implementation of responsibility-sensitive equality within a framework of prior rights and duties, and making the crucial point that the payoffs associated with choices should not be viewed simply as a given.
- Hugh Lazenby, ‘One Kiss Too Many? Giving, Luck Egalitarianism and Other-affecting Choice’, The Journal of Political Philosophy vol. 18, no. 3 (2010)
Lazenby explores a central instance of the problem of 'other-affecting choice' for luck egalitarianism, arguing that the problem highlights tensions between the value of equality as luck egalitarians conceive it and a range of other important values, and that the luck egalitarian position must be very carefully worked out if it is to avoid devastating objection. Lazenby's is one of a number of articles criticising luck egalitarianism not so much for its unpalatable intuitive implications or for its core commitments so much as for the tensions or incoherences that are immanent within it.
- Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, ‘(Luck and relational) egalitarians of the world, unite!’, presented at the 2016 workshop for Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy. Available here.
Lippert-Rasmussen attempts to transcend the dispute between luck and relational egalitarians by formulating a view that purports to incorporate insights from both views, and argues that this 'ecumenical view' is most naturally motivated by luck egalitarian motives.
- Derek Parfit, ‘Equality or Priority?’, given as The Lindley Lecture (University of Kansas, 1991)
Parfit's seminal lecture describes and defends 'the priority view', one of the two leading rivals (alongside sufficientarianism) to strictly egalitarian accounts of broadly egalitarian political commitments. Parfit motivates the priority view in large part by appeal to the 'levelling down objection' to egalitarianism. Both the priority view and the levelling down objection have since played large roles in debates about distributive justice and the value of equality. There is now an large literature on the priority view and its plausibility as an alternative to equality.
- Robert Huseby, ‘Sufficiency: Restated and Defended;, The Journal of Political Philosophy vol. 18, no. 2 (2010)
Huseby describes and defends 'sufficientarianism', the other of the two leading rivals (alongside prioritarianism) to strictly egalitarian accounts of broadly egalitarian political commitments. Huseby describes a distinctive 'two-threshold' sufficientarianism and defends it from several of the objections that sufficientarianism has attracted. Huseby's is one of a number of articles on sufficientarianism, inspired primarily by an article by Harry Frankfurt (‘Equality as a Moral ideal’, Ethics vol. 98, no. 1 [1987]).
- Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, chapter 7, section I (Basic Books, 1974)
Nozick criticises 'end-state' theories of distributive justice, which must, he argues, "forbid capitalist acts between consenting adults", as well as operating a scheme of taxation—something that he suggests is "on a par with forced labour". Instead, Nozick argues, the correct theory of distributive justice is an historical 'entitlement theory'.
Hide further reading ⇑
III. Democracy
Democracy is widely supposed to have a special kind of legitimacy, one that other forms of government lack, whatever other virtues they may have. But is the supposition defensible, or is it merely the product of familiarity with democratic structures—or even of a kind of ideological conditioning—on the part of citizens in democratic societies? What is the source of the authority of democratically elected governments and the laws they enact? Does the answer to that question also adequately explain why democracy is distinctively legitimate and indeed generally superior to (e.g.) a benevolent dictatorship? And does it explain why we can be obliged to comply even with unjust laws? These are the questions we consider this week.
Question: Is democracy the only legitimate form of government? Why?
Priority reading (Hide)
- Daniel Viehoff, ‘Democratic equality and political authority’, Philosophy & Public Affairs 42 (2014), pp. 337–375
Democrats believe that the egalitarian character of democratic procedures explains the authority of democratic decisions. Rejecting arguments for democracy’s authority from fairness and the value of public equal respect, Viehoff appeals instead to the value of relational equality and the resultant need to secure “coordination without subjection”.
- Richard Arneson ‘Defending the Purely Instrumental Account of Democratic Legitimacy’, Journal of Political Philosophy 11 (2003), pp. 122–132
Arneson briefly sets out his instrumentalist defence of democracy, which appeals only to the fact that it gives rise to the best results over the long run (where ‘best results’ is understood in terms of fulfilment of fundamental rights) and then offers some clarifications and replies to objections.
- Joshua Cohen, ‘Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy’, in Matravers and Pike (eds), Debates in Contemporary Political Philosophy (Routledge, 2002)
Identifying three attractive democratic conditions, Cohen argues that Rawl’s appeal to fairness provides an unsatisfying justification for them. Instead, he suggests, they are best justified by reference to an ideal deliberative procedure, for which he sets out formal and substantive conditions. He goes on to answer four objections, from sectarianism, incoherence, injustice, and irrelevance.
- Iris Marion Young, Inclusion and Democracy (Oxford, 2002), chapter 1
After briefly criticising what she calls the ‘aggregative model’ of democracy, Young turns her attention in this framing introductory chapter to the ‘deliberative model’, identifying core conditions of the democratic process on that model. She argues that this model accounts better for the connection many take there to be between democracy and justice and of the esteem in which democracy is held, because democratic deliberation under the core conditions will tend to produce just decisions. She goes on to argue that the objection that democratic deliberation produces just decisions only when justice already prevails can be addressed by deliberative democrats, but only if they avoid certain pitfalls in their conception of the deliberative model.
- David Estlund, Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework (Princeton, 2007)
Starting from the assumption that there are correct answers about what, politically, ought to be done (which assumption, Estlund argues, favours democracy over other fair procedures such as flipping a coin), Estlund defends democracy against the challenge from ‘epistocracy’ (rule by the knowers) that this assumption would seem to justify. The key premiss is a ‘qualified acceptability requirement’, which, Estlund contends, only democracy passes.
- Thomas Christiano, ‘The Authority of Democracy’, Journal of Political Philosophy 12 (2004), pp. 266–290.
Christiano argues that democracy's authority is justified by a principle of justice that calls for public realisation of equal advancement of interests. He argues against instrumentalism on the grounds that it ignores the justice specified by this principle and against consent theory on the grounds that it concedes too much to injustice in another way. He concludes with reflections on the limits of democratic authority that can be derived from the same fundamental principle.
- Laura Valentini, ‘Justice, Disagreement, and Democracy’, British Journal of Political Science 43 (2013), pp. 177–199
Valentini argues that democracy is at best an instrumental requirement of equal respect for persons under circumstances of what she calls ‘thin reasonable disagreement’, but it is an intrinsic requirement of equal respect for persons under circumstances of ‘thick reasonable disagreement’.
- Zofia Stemplowska and Adam Swift, ‘Dethroning Democratic Legitimacy’, in Sobel, Vallentyne, and Wall (eds.), Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, Volume 4 (Oxford, 2018)
Stemplowska and Swift defend a ‘balancing view’ of the respective claims of justice and legitimacy in determining the permissibility of enforcing a decision. They oppose this to what they call the ‘conventional view’—that the democratic pedigree of a decision makes it permissibly enforceable, except if it is gravely unjust—which they subject to a barrage of objections.
- Sor-hoon Tan, ‘Why Equality and Which Inequalities? A Modern Confucian Approach to Democracy’, Philosophy East and West 66 (2016), pp. 488–514
Tan argues that rather than insisting on an abstract ideal of equality as an uncontroversial foundation for democracy, we would do better to focus on what is problematic about particular inequalities and defend democracy as a remedy. This, she argues, clears the way to a possible instrumentalist Confucian defence of democracy as necessary under certain conditions for good government despite Confucianism’s rejection of equality as an abstract value.
Hide priority reading ⇑
Further reading (Hide)
- Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Why Deliberative Democracy? (Princeton, 2004)
- Niko Kolodny, ‘Rule Over None’ Part I and Part II, Philosophy & Public Affairs 42 (2014), pp. 195–229 and 287–336
- Thomas Christiano, The Constitution of Equality (Oxford, 2008)
- Chantal Mouffe, The Democratic Paradox (Verso, 2000)
- Bonnie Honig, Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics (Cornell, 1993), chapter 5
Honig claims that Rawlsian justice ‘closes down political spaces’ in assuming that justice as fairness and its assumptions can be made to fit those upon whom it is imposed “without remainder” and then treating symptoms of a lack of such fit as loci for punishment rather than politics. Inclusive, democratic commitments are better served, she argues, by institutions that “shift and proliferate the sites of politics.”
- John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, revised edition (Harvard, 1999), especially section 194
- Philip Pettit, On the People's Terms (Cambridge, 2012)
- Daniel Viehoff, ‘Procedure and Outcome in the Justification of Democracy’, The Journal of Political Philosophy vol. 19, no. 2 (2011)
Hide further reading ⇑
IV. Liberalism
Liberalism is the dominant ideology of contemporary Anglophone and western European societies. It is characterised by a commitment to familiar rights to bodily integrity; to freedom of thought, expression, and conscience; to private property; and to the rule of law, among others. But what is the best account of liberalism's moral basis? Is it founded in the value of autonomy, a general utilitarianism, the way it promotes its citizens' flourishing, or in the way it handles religious difference—or simply in the protections it affords against tyranny? How powerful are any of these arguments?
Question: What is the best argument for liberal institutions?
Priority reading (Hide)
- John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, revised edition (Harvard, 1999), sections 2–4, 24, 26, 39
In these sections of his masterpiece, Rawls sets out the main ideas of his theory of 'justice as fairness' and explains how the contractualist apparatus of the 'original position' yields the liberal priority of the basic liberties. All of chapters I, III, and IV are relevant, but these sections will give you the basics.
- Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Clarendon, 1986), chapters 14–15
In these final chapters of Raz's influential Millian defence of liberalism, Raz describes an ideal of individual autonomy and its relation to value, and then explains how it underpins liberal institutions, including a version of J.S. Mill's famous Harm Principle.
- Martha Nussbaum, ‘Aristotelian Social Democracy’, in Douglass, Mara, and Richardson (eds.), Liberalism and the Good (Routledge, 1990)
Nussbaum defends a liberal democratic political theory on the basis of a 'vague thick' account of the good for humans. Nussbaum's Aristotelian perfectionist liberalism puts her somewhere between Rawls and Raz.
- Judith Shklar, ‘The Liberalism of Fear’, in Rosenblum (ed.), Liberalism and the Moral Life (Harvard, 1989)
Shklar argues for a conception of liberalism that founds it on the principle that above all else, the weak are to be protected from the cruelty of the powerful. Although she eschews seemingly more exalted defences, her account nevertheless has interesting points of contact with ‘public reason liberalism’, republicanism, conservativism, and democratic theory.
- Thomas Nagel, ‘Rawls on Justice’, The Philosophical Review vol. 82, no. 2 (1973)
This early review of A Theory of Justice puts pressure on Rawls’s exclusion of conceptions of the good from the original position and on the conditions of the original position that allow derivation of the difference principle.
- Jonathan Quong, Liberalism without Perfection (Oxford, 2010), chapters 2–3
Quong attacks Raz’s perfectionist liberalism on the grounds that it fails to secure an adequately robust defence of liberal freedoms and that it allows anti-liberal state activity. He then argues against perfectionism in general that it is objectionably paternalistic.
- F.A. von Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (Routledge, 2006), chapters 1–3
Hayek is one of the intellectual founders of contemporary free-market conservatism (although see The Constitution of Liberty's Postscript). In these chapters he argues for the individual liberties associated with capitalism on the basis that the market activities of individuals exercising these liberties produces enormous material, cultural, and intellectual benefits that it is beyond the capacity of any central organiser to produce.
- Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Basic Books, 1974), pp. 26–35, 48–51, 150–174
Nozick defends libertarianism on Kantian deontological grounds, arguing from an account of individuals as bearers of stringent self-ownership rights against others' interference (in the first two extracts) to the view that "taxation of earnings from labour is on a par with forced labour" (in the third extract). The book is written in lively, engaging prose, and is perhaps the most influential treatise in contemporary Anglophone academic political philosophy after Rawls's A Theory of Justice.
- G.A. Cohen, Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality (Cambridge, 1995), chapter 10
This chapter, part of a book-length attack on the arguments of Nozick’s Anarchy, State, and Utopia, focuses on the foundational Nozickean thesis of self-ownership. Cohen has already argued in earlier chapters that self-ownership does not straightforwardly generate inegalitarian conclusions; here he focuses on undermining the appeal of self-ownership by distinguishing it from nearby ideas with which it might be conflated.
Hide priority reading ⇑
Further reading (Hide)
- John Locke, Second Treatise of Government (1689), chapters 1–5, 7–11 (For more accessible but still scholarly revision, see here.)
Locke's liberalism is founded on an account of natural rights, which give the end of government—to secure them in a way that is unlikely in the state of nature—and set its limits. Locke is the grandfather of one important strand of contemporary libertarianism.
- J.S. Mill, On Liberty (1859), chapters 2–4
Mill's On Liberty is one of the great defences of liberalism. Mill argues for some of the central liberal freedoms on several grounds, including: that self-direction and self-development according to one's own ideas is intrinsically valuable; that it is also the best route to well-being, since no one way of life is best for everyone; and that the conditions of freedom of speech and way of life are necessary for truths to be discovered and false orthodoxies challenged.
- Ronald Dworkin, ‘Liberalism’, in his A Matter of Principle (Harvard, 1985)
Dworkin defends liberalism (which, in the contemporary US tradition, he contrasts with conservatism) on the basis of an interpretation of the principle of 'equal concern and respect' that takes it to require neutrality on questions of the good life.
- Michael Otsuka, Libertarianism without Inequality (Oxford, 2003), chapter 1
Drawing on the work of G.A. Cohen and Robert Nozick, Otsuka argues that a libertarian commitment to self-ownership does not have the inegalitarian consequences usually associated with it, thanks to the distinction between self-ownership and world-ownership and the plausibility of applying egalitarian principles to the latter.
- Jeremy Waldron, ‘Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism’, The Philosophical Quarterly vol. 37, no. 147 (1987)
Waldron argues that liberalism is essentially a view about enforcement of a political order legitimate, and that its fundamental commitment is to the idea that the social order should be capable of being made acceptable to every individual member of it.
- John Tomasi, Free Market Fairness (Princeton, 2012), chapters 1–2
Tomasi sketches an engaging, intentionally tendentious account of the development of liberalism, contrasting the classical liberalism of Locke and (later) Hayek with the contemporary 'high liberalism' of Rawls and Dworkin. His purpose is to motivate his own hybrid view, 'market democracy', but for now you can treat these chapters simply as a readable overview of some central conflicts within liberalism.
Hide further reading ⇑
V. Politics and pluralism
Contemporary political societies are home to a wide diversity of views about how life is to be lived—what is sometimes described as ‘moral pluralism’. At the extreme, this diversity may be a factor in the collapse of trust in institutions and a resort to violence. How should political theory and institutions deal with pluralism? This week's topic addresses this question, with a focus on ‘public reason liberalism’, according to which political legitimacy depends upon the compatibility of political principles with a wide range of conflicting views.
Question: Can liberal political philosophy adequately take into account the fact that different people have different and incompatible views about the good and the right?
Priority reading (Hide)
- John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Harvard, 2001), Parts I and V
In this overview of his version of public reason liberalism, Rawls sets out the main ideas he employs in building a political conception of justice, and explains how the conception can be the focus of an 'overlapping consensus' of conflicting reasonable moral views. Rawls argues in more detail for the public reason liberalism summarised in these sections in Political Liberalism (Columbia, 1996), and elaborates his account of public reason in particular in ‘The Idea of Public Reason Revisited’, in The Law of Peoples (Harvard, 1999).
- Jonathan Quong, Liberalism without Perfection (Oxford, 2010), chapter 1
Quong offers a helpful survey of the various positions available in debates between public reason liberals (or ‘political liberals’) and ‘comprehensive liberals’.
- Charles Larmore, ‘Political Liberalism’, Political Theory vol. 18, no. 3 (1990)
In an early defence of public reason liberalism, Larmore appeals to a Kantian ideal of equal respect for persons as a basis for liberal neutrality. The basic idea is that equal respect demands that the coercive institutions of a state must be justifiable from the point of view of each person, because otherwise they are a matter of mere coercion, which treats others as mere means, not ends. In this way, Larmore hopes to find a moral basis for the traditional liberal separation of church and state that avoids appealing merely to pragmatic considerations, or to scepticism about religious claims, or to controversial conceptions of individual autonomy.
- Christopher Eberle, Religious Conviction in Liberal Politics (Cambridge, 2002), chapters 4–5
Eberle argues that respect for her fellow citizens does not, contrary to the claims of Rawlsian public reason liberals, require a person to refuse to support coercive laws for which she can offer no public justification.
- Martha Nussbaum, ‘Perfectionist Liberalism and Political Liberalism’, Philosophy & Public Affairs vol. 39, no. 1 (2011)
Nussbaum defends public reason liberalism against the criticisms of comprehensive liberals such as Joseph Raz. Helpfully, she devotes special attention to the difficult question of what distinguishes a 'reasonable' view according to public reason liberals, who argue that political institutions must be justifiable from all reasonable points of view, but need not be from unreasonable points of view.
- David Enoch, ‘Against Public Reason’, in Sobel, Vallentyne, and Wall (eds.), Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, vol. 1 (Oxford, 2015)
Enoch trenchantly criticises public reason liberalism in general, arguing that although its proponents are motivated by powerful concerns about authority and liberty, they misunderstand these, and cannot address them adequately within their favoured framework.
- Japa Pallikkathayil, ‘Neither Perfectionism nor Political Liberalism’, Philosophy & Public Affairs vol. 44, no. 3 (2016)
Pallikkathayil defends a ‘comprehensive anti-perfectionist’ Kantian approach to the kinds of problems that are the focus of the debate between perfectionists and political liberals. She argues that this approach avoids certain objections to political liberalism and at the same time does a better job than political liberalism of explaining what‘s wrong with perfectionist liberalism and policies.
- Collis Tahzib, ‘Perfectionism: Political not Metaphysical’, Philosophy & Public Affairs vol. 47, no. 2 (2019)
Tahzib argues that liberal perfectionism can be defended on political liberal foundations, contrary to the prevailing assumptions of the debate between political liberals and perfectionists.
Hide priority reading ⇑
Further reading (Hide)
- Susan Moller Okin, Justice, Gender, and the Family (Basic Books, 1989)
This influential critique of twentieth-century liberal theorising about social justice argues that the impression of inclusivity and gender equality conceals a fatal neglect of questions about gender roles and injustice within the family.
- Sri Aurobindo, ‘The Right of Association’, in The Complete Works of Sri Aurobindo (Sri Aurobindo Ashram Press, 1997), vol. 8, pp. 67–83
In the course of a defence of the revolutionary Anushilan Samiti pro-independence organisation, Aurobindo casts liberal freedoms as necessary preconditions for the achievement of moksha (Hindu spiritual liberation), and so provides a religious justification for liberalism and some support for Rawls's claims. The idea that Eastern ideas of spiritual freedom and Western ideas of external freedom are complementary is a theme of Aurobindo's political writings; see also his Complete Works, vol. 13.
- Hamid Hadji Haidar, Liberalism and Islam (Palgrave Macmillan, 2008), pp. 187–192 ('Conclusion')
Haidar's book considers the compatibility of Shiite Islam and the liberalisms of, first, J.S. Mill and, second, John Rawls. Haidar finds Shiite Islam theoretically incompatible with Millian liberalism and partially compatible with Rawlsian liberalism, although neither is justifiable from the Shiite point of view. At the practical level, Haidar draws the interesting conclusion that there is no practical incompatibility between Shiite Muslim citizens' commitments and fully liberal institutions within a pluralistic society, but there is such an incompatibility within a Muslim society. This extract summarises these conclusions.
- Joseph Raz, ‘Facing Diversity: The Case of Epistemic Abstinence’, Philosophy & Public Affairs vol. 19, no. 1 (1990)
Rawls's public reason liberalism is officially committed to 'epistemic abstinence' (taking no stand on the truth claims about the good and the right), 'shallow foundations' (working from certain values that are already present in public political culture), and the 'autonomy' of the political view from wider moral questions. Raz objects to all these features of public reason liberalism, and concludes that Rawls's approach is to be rejected. You need not read beyond page 31.
- Gerald F. Gaus and Kevin Vallier, ‘The roles of religious conviction in a publicly justified polity;, Philosophy & Social Criticism vol. 35, no. 1–2 (2009)
Gaus and Vallier argue for a 'convergence' conception of public reason liberalism that is, they suggest, less hostile to religious reasons in the justification of laws and policies than 'consensus' conceptions, such as Rawls's, are.
- Henry Rosemont, Jr., ‘Whose Democracy? Which Rights? A Confucian Critique of Modern Western Liberalism’, in Shun and Wong (eds.), Confucian Ethics (Cambridge, 2004)
Rosemont argues that Confucianism provides insight into the possibility of a universalistic but non-liberal theory of rights and democracy. This theory deprioritises the notions of autonomy and individualism as it is construed within liberal theory, together with the associated 'first-generation' negative rights (including rights of economic freedom) stressed by liberalism—at the cost, Rosemont argues, of social and economic well being. Instead, the Confucian account emphasises the socially constituted aspects of the self and their accompanying responsibilities of care, and accordingly prioritises positive social and economic rights. Rosemont also sees the value of self-government as potentially better realised within a Confucian system than under Western liberal democratic institutions.
Hide further reading ⇑
VI. Injustice and oppression
Even though Rawls, Nozick, Cohen, and other key Anglophone political philosophers of the late 20th century were explicitly concerned with justice, an important strand of critique of work in the Rawlsian tradition argues that it fails to attend to or even appropriately conceptualise injustice. The work of feminists has been particularly influential in formulating and propelling this critique. This week, we turn to this critique, with a particular focus on the concept of oppression and the question whether liberals in the Rawlsian tradition are in a position to address or even understand it adequately.
Question: What is oppression? Can a liberal theory of social justice adequately address it?
Priority reading (Hide)
- Marilyn Frye, ‘Oppression’, in Terence Ball, Richard Dagger, and Daniel I O'Neill (eds.), Ideals and Ideologies: A Reader, Ninth Edition (Routledge, 2016). Text also available online here. (9pp)
Frye defends an account of oppression as subjection to a certain structure of freedom-restriction on the basis of group membership and in order to further the interests of other groups, and distinguishes oppression so understood from various other forms of unfreedom and disadvantage. She is particularly concerned to debunk the reply to claims that women are oppressed that consists in arguing that men are too.
- Iris Marion Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton, 1990), chapters 1–2
This is a classic of contemporary political philosophy, arguing against the 'distributive paradigm' of theorising about justice, according to which justice is always a matter of who gets what. Young argues that justice is also a matter of culture, political decisionmaking, and division of labour. In the second chapter, she analyses the notion of oppression, which she takes to be essential for identifying non-distributive injustices, and distinguishes five ways in which oppression is manifested.
- Charles W. Mills, The Racial Contract (Ithaca, 1997), chapters 1–2
A ferocious, coruscating critique of contemporary liberal theory and politics. Mills argues powerfully that liberalism developed within the historical frame of a 'racial contract' that violently excluded and exploited non-whites, and that its central commitments continue to reflect the oppressive and exploitative features of that contract.
- Iris Marion Young, Responsibility for Justice (Oxford, 2011), chapter 4
Distinguishing responsibility as liability from a forward-looking concept of responsibility, Young argues for a model of responsibility for addressing structural injustice of the latter kind.
- Martha Nussbaum, Sex and Social Justice (Oxford, 1999), chapter 2
Nussbaum defends liberalism against a variety of feminist criticisms, arguing that feminists should embrace liberalism's core commitments and press for liberal practice to be made more consistent with them, rather than abandoned.
- Anca Gheaus, ‘Gender Justice’, Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy vol. 6, no. 2 (2012)
Gheaus defends a novel principle of 'gender justice' designed to capture the nature of a wide range of gender-based injustices, founding it on core liberal ideas of autonomy and freedom. The flagship claim is that a society is unjust if a gender-neutral lifestyle is more costly than a gendered lifestyle.
- Dorothea Gadëke, ‘Who should fight domination? Individual responsibility and structural injustice’, Politics, Philosophy & Economics vol. 20, no. 2 (2021)
Drawing on her analysis of domination as a structural phemonenon, Gadëke argues against outcome-based, capacity-based, and Iris Marion Young’s social connection model of responsibility for fighting injustice in favour of a kind of hybrid view that she thinks avoids problems with the others.
- David Estlund, ‘What’s Unjust about Structural Injustice?’, Ethics vol. 134, no. 3 (2024)
Estlund presses what he calls the “reach/grievance” puzzle for anyone who thinks there can be structural injustice: either structural injustices involve wrongdoing, but in that case fewer cases are aptly described as cases of structural injustices than is typically supposed; or structural justices don’t need to involve wrongdoing, in which case ‘grievance attitudes’ such as anger and resentment are out of place as reactions to them. His intention is not to reject the possibility of structural injustice, but to present a challenge for those attracted to analysis in terms of it. You can find philosophers including Sally Haslanger discussing this article at the Pea Soup blog.
Hide priority reading ⇑
Further reading (Hide)
- Catharine McKinnon, Towards a Feminist Theory of the State (Harvard, 1989), chapter 8
McKinnon argues that the liberal state's law reflects and entrenches women's subordination by assuming the kind of social equality that obtains only among men, even in areas where it would seem to be progressive in this respect.
- Clare Chambers, Sex, Culture, and Justice: The Limits of Choice (Penn State, 2008)
Chambers makes a distinction between first-order and second-order autonomy and argues that attention to the distinction reveals certain kinds of injustice that core liberal commitments should make them willing to legislate against, despite the apparent illiberalism of such legislation.
- Anita Silvers, ‘No Talent? Beyond the Worst Off! A Diverse Theory of Justice for Disability’, in Brownlee and Cureton (eds.), Disability and Disadvantage (Oxford, 2009)
Silver argues that traditional social contract theories of justice deal badly with cases of 'outliers', who don't conform to the paradigm of normality that the theories assume. She defends an approach that prioritises cultivating the trust required for cooperation, and argues that this approach allows the embracing of difference in a way that the traditional approaches do not.
- Sally Haslanger, ‘Gender and Race: (What) Are They? (What) Do We Want Them To Be?’, Noûs vol. 34, no. 1 (2000)
Haslanger proposes analyses of gender and race for the purposes of critical feminist and antiracist politics, setting aside attempts to find some biological or other naturalistic basis for gender or race terms and attempts to capture everyday understandings implicit in the use of those terms.
- Lawrence Blum, "I'm not a Racist, But..." The Moral Quandary of Race (Cornell, 2002), chapter 8
Earlier in this book, Blum argues that there is no scientific underpinning for the concept of race and that it provides a morally troubling way of thinking about people even when not accompanied by racism. In this chapter he claims that we must nevertheless recognise the way in which certain groups of people have shared experiences of oppression as a result of the fact that they have been treated as if they were members of a single race, and proposes referring to such groups as ‘racialised’ rather than ‘races’ as a way to do this.
- K. Anthony Appiah, ‘Race, Culture, Identity: Misunderstood Connections’, in Appiah and Gutmann, Color Conscious: The Political Morality of Race (Princeton, 1996)
Appiah traces some of the history of the concept of race and argues that there is no clear set of criteria or underlying biological basis that will do the job of discriminating between the people the concept is used to discriminate between. He goes on to propose an account of racial identity that makes central a history of association with presumed racial essence, but remains sceptical about the value of such identities.
- Naomi Zack, ‘Can Third Wave Feminism Be Inclusive? Intersectionality, its Problems and New Directions’, in Alcoff and Kittay (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Feminist Philosophy (Blackwell, 2007)
Zack describes, first, the critique of feminism that it has excluded the experience of non-white women, and, second, the emergence of the ideas of 'intersectionality' and anti-essentialism in response. She expresses doubts about the response, and proposes a relational definition of 'woman' that addresses the doubts without falling foul of the original critique.
- Robin Zheng, ‘What is My Role in Changing the System? A New Model of Responsibility for Structural Injustice’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice vol. 21 (2018)
Zheng argues for a model of responsibility for structural injustice according to which role-bearers are responsible for addressing structural injustice in virtue of occupying those roles, in contrast to Iris Marion Young's ‘social connections model’.
Hide further reading ⇑
VII. Republicanism and domination
Like liberals, contemporary republicans defend a political philosophy in which freedom is the central value. But they conceive of freedom in a distinctive way: not as a matter of the absence of constraints, or even (in the manner of proponents of so-called ‘positive liberty’) as a matter of self-realisation, but rather in terms of non-domination or non-subjection to arbitrary power. This week we consider that conception of freedom and the political theory built upon it, asking whether republicanism offers a way to avoid some of the problems with negative liberty-focused liberalism that we have been discussing to date, and what problems republicanism might have itself.
Question: How do republicanism and liberalism differ? Does the former solve the latter's problems?
Priority reading (Hide)
- Philip Pettit, On the People's Terms (Cambridge, 2012), chapters 1–2
Pettit has been defending and developing a republican political theory over the past two decades. In this recent statement of his view, he makes it clear that the characteristic republican emphasis on freedom as non-domination provides a moral basis for key political commitments.
- Cécile Laborde, Critical Republicanism: The Hijab Controversy and Political Philosophy (Oxford 2008), chapter 7
- Arthur Ripstein, ‘Authority and Coercion’, Philosophy & Public Affairs vol. 32, no. 1 (2004)
- Marilyn Friedman, ‘Pettit's Civic Republicanism and Male Domination’, in Laborde and Maynor (eds.), Republicanism and Political Theory (Wiley, 2008)
Friedman argues that Pettit’s conception of domination is overinclusive, since capacities to interfere arbitrarily in others’ choices are ubiquitous—indeed, they are valuable in the case of people who are dependent on caretakers—and Pettit thinks vulnerability to domination can come with group membership alone. Pettit’s approach, Friedman suggests, demonstrates an insensitivity to the important role of dependence on others in human life generally. She goes on to spell out a more qualified, individualistic account of domination than Pettit’s.
- Ian Carter, ‘How are Power and Unfreedom Related?’, in Laborde and Maynor (eds.), Republicanism and Political Theory (Wiley, 2008)
Carter argues that the ‘negative’ conception of freedom that liberals treat as fundamental can make sense of the judgments about unfreedom that motivate republicans to reject it in favour of an account of freedom as non-domination or non-subjection, and is, moreover, preferable to such republican accounts because of the justificatory role it can play in political theory.
- Niko Kolodny, ‘Being Under the Power of Others’, in Elazar and Rousselière (eds.), Republicanism and the Future of Democracy (Cambridge, 2019)
Kolodny argues that the republican argument for state legitimacy that appeals to domination fails insofar as it can’t explain why the state doesn’t objectionably dominate its citizens, or why a state of nature couldn’t be sufficiently free of domination if the state could. He proposes that what’s really at the root of republicanism is “a broader anxiety about standing in relations of social inferiority” with other individuals.
- Dorothea Gadëke, ‘Does a Mugger Dominate? Episodic Power and the Structural Dimension of Domination’, Journal of Political Philosophy vol. 28, no. 2 (2020)
Using the title's question to pose a dilemma for republican accounts of domination, Gadëke argues that domination is a structurally constituted rather than ‘mere interactional’ form of power, and that thinking of it this way helps to rescue domination-focused accounts from various problems as well as to suit them for critical social analysis. She also makes a valuable distinction between interpersonal and systemic domination.
- Christian List and Laura Valentini, ‘Freedom as Independence’, Ethics vol. 126, no. 4 (2016)
After analysing the logical space in which different negative conceptions of freedom can be located, List and Valentini defend a conception of freedom as independence that differs from liberal freedom in that it incorporates a robustness condition and from republican freedom in that it is non-moralised.
- Sharon R. Krause, ‘Beyond non-domination: Agency, inequality and the meaning of freedom’, Philosophy & Social Criticism vol. 39, no. 2 (2013)
Krause argues that republican non-domination is too narrow an account of freedom to capture important aspects of the unfreedom of subordinate groups, because social constraints on these groups do not always involve intention or control on the part of others. Krause goes on to argue that the problem lies in the relatively unsophisticated picture of agency implicit in standard republican analyses of freedom.
- Melvin L. Rogers, ‘Race, Domination, and Republicanism‘, in Allen and Somanathan (eds.), Difference without domination: pursuing justice in diverse democracies (Chicago, 2020)
Rogers argues that attention to African American political thought reveals lessons for republicanism, particularly on the need for more subtle and contextually-sensitive accounts of republican civic virtue, for analyses of the reversibility of domination and of culturally encoded domination alongside the more familiar analyses of domination by other agents.
- Lori Watson, ‘On Domination’, in Chang and Srinivasan (eds.), Conversations in Philosophy, Law, and Politics (Oxford, 2024)
Watson draws a contrast between the republican analysis of domination and the analyses found within the feminist tradition, which she defends as capable of capturing a wider range of domination than the republican analysis. Watson also offers helpful remarks on the relations between domination, subordination, and oppression.
Hide priority reading ⇑
Further reading (Hide)
- Frank Lovett, A General Theory of Domination and Justice (Oxford, 2010), chapters 2–4
- Christopher McCammon, ‘Domination: A Rethinking’, Ethics vol. 125, no. 4 (2015)
- Robert E. Goodin and Frank Jackson, ‘Freedom from Fear’, Philosophy & Public Affairs vol. 35, no. 3 (2007)
- Philip Pettit, ‘Republican Freedom: Three Axioms, Four Theorems’, in Laborde and Maynor (eds.), Republicanism and Political Theory (Wiley, 2008)
Pettit sets out in clear terms the republican account of freedom that he favours before responding critically to attempts to capture the republican idea of freedom in negative libertarian terms (see e.g. the Carter chapter in the priority reading list).
- Thomas W. Simpson, ‘The Impossibility of Republican Freedom’, Philosophy & Public Affairs vol. 45, no. 1 (2017)
- Philip Pettit, ‘Freedom and Probability: A Comment on Goodin and Jackson’, Philosophy & Public Affairs vol. 36, no. 2 (2008)
- Frank Lovett and Philip Pettit, ‘Preserving Republican Freedom: A Reply to Simpson’, Philosophy & Public Affairs vol. 46, no. 4 (2018)
- Thomas W. Simpson, ‘Freedom and Trust: A Rejoinder to Lovett and Pettit’, Philosophy & Public Affairs vol. 47, no. 4 (2019)
Hide further reading ⇑
VIII. Political realism and the concept of the political
Political realists oppose themselves to what they see as the dominant approach in contemporary Anglophone political philosophy, according to which political philosophy is a matter of applying prior moral principles. By contrast with this ‘political moralist’ approach, realists argue that the political is in some sense an autonomous domain, distinctively concerned with questions of power and legitimacy, and calling accordingly for modes of political philosophising adjusted to its distinctive features. Political realism is increasingly popular, but it is difficult to gain a clear understanding of the realist critique of political moralism. This week we try to do that and to assess that critique.
Question: Does most contemporary Anglophone political philosophy misconstrue the political? If so, how, and what is to be done about it?
Priority reading (Hide)
- Bernard Williams, ‘Realism and Moralism in Political Theory’ and ‘The Liberalism of Fear’, in In the Beginning Was the Deed (Princeton, 2005)
Williams argues against political theorising that treats it as merely applied moral philosophy, and for understanding political philosophy instead primarily in terms of the “first political question” of securing the conditions of cooperation and meeting the associated ‘basic legitimation demand’. He defends a ‘liberalism of fear’ within this frame, as uniquely flexible and aware of the nature of the political.
- Raymond Geuss, Philosophy and Real Politics (Princeton, 2008)
Geuss defends a realist approach to political theory that views politics through the lens of questions about power, historical feasibility, and prevailing mechanisms of legitimation. He identifies five tasks for political philosophy based upon this approach, and then critiques the approach of contemporary ‘analytic’ political philosophy, focusing on the case of Rawls.
- Chantal Mouffe, On the Political (Routledge, 2005), chapter 2
Mouffe argues that antagonism is an eradicable condition of political association, and therefore that the aim of democratic politics is not the establishment of rational consensus, contrary to what Mouffe sees as the dominant liberal theoretical approach, but of ‘agonistic relations’: a way of taming destructive enmity through adversarial political institutions.
- David Owen, ‘Realism in Ethics and Politics: Bernard Williams, Political Theory, and the Critique of Morality’, in Matt Sleat (ed.), Politics Recovered: Realist Thought in Theory and Practice (Columbia, 2018)
Owen offers helpful contextualisation and interpretation of William’s political realism.
- Paul Sagar, ‘Legitimacy and Domination’, in Matt Sleat (ed.), Politics Recovered: Realist Thought in Theory and Practice (Columbia, 2018)
Sagar discusses the prospects for ‘internalist’ accounts of legitimacy according to which legitimacy is a function of the beliefs of those subject to power. He argues that internalists can rebut ‘happy slaves’-type objections more easily than might be supposed, and defends a way of going beyond Williams’s ‘critical theory principle’ test for appeals to subjects’ legitimating beliefs that is indebted to Haslanger’s work on ideology.
- Lorna Finlayson, The Political is Political (Rowman & Littlefield, 2015), chapter 5
Finlayson criticises the realist and non-ideal theory trends in contemporary political philosophy on the grounds that they preclude “deep dissent” by placing limits “on the extent to which deviation from dominant modes of political philosophy is even thinkable”. This, she says, effectively forces a false choice between utopian criticism of the status quo or realistic acceptance of it.
- Ilaria Cozzaglio and Amanda R. Greene, ‘Can power be self-legitimating? Political realism in Hobbes, Weber, and Williams’, European Journal of Philosophy 27 (2019)
Cozzaglio and Greene examine Williams’s reasons for departing from the forms of political realism found in Hobbes and Weber, arguing that in fact the Weberian form is superior to Williams’s, which must either turn out to be moralistic or else collapse into Hobbes’s position, which cannot distinguish between legitimate and illegitimate domination. The article offers interesting and illuminating analysis of the authors it discusses as well as of the conditions of political society that give rise to demands for legitimacy in the first place.
- Enzo Rossi, ‘Being realistic and demanding the impossible’, Constellations vol. 26 (2019)
After a brief characterisation of the general tenets of political realism, Rossi distinguishes three sub-types of realism each prioritising a different political problem. Rossi goes on to describe the sub-type he calls ‘radical realism’ in more detail, arguing that it can have more radical implications than its critics claim, even as it avoids the objectionable kind of utopianism realists associate with political moralism.
Hide priority reading ⇑
Further reading (Hide)
- John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Harvard, 2001), section 1.
Rawls distinguishes four roles for political philosophy: to identify a basis for agreement to underpin social cooperation on a footing of mutual respect; to enable us to understand ourselves as members of a political community; to reconcile us to our social world; and to probe the limits of practical political possibility. Rawls focuses in particular on these roles in the context of the ‘fact of reasonable pluralism’.
- Mark Philp, ‘Realism without Illusions’, Political Theory vol. 40, no. 5 (2012)
- Matt Sleat, ‘Realism, Liberalism and Non-ideal Theory Or, Are there Two Ways to do Realistic Political Theory?’, Political Studies 64, no. 1 (2016)
Sleat clarifies the distinction between political realism and non-ideal theorising in contemporary political philosophy, arguing that only the former represents a fundamental challenge to contemporary liberal theorising.
- Jeremy Waldron, ‘Political Political Theory’, The Journal of Political Philosophy vol. 21, no. 1 (2013)
Waldron argues for greater emphasis on the study of institutions and political processes as opposed to the great political ends (justice, liberty, equality, etc.), and in particular on the question how to choose between various political institutional possibilities, as for example when thinking about devolution in the UK—a question about which “the 57 different varieties of luck-egalitarianism” studied in Oxford have nothing to say.
- Richard Bellamy, Liberalism and Pluralism: Towards a Politics of Compromise (Routledge, 2002), chapter 2
Bellamy argues that Rawls fails to appreciate the way in which citizens' religious affiliations may be in tension with liberal political principles as well as tensions within those political principles (e.g. between different liberties) that cannot be resolved philosophically. He claims that this analysis reveals the way in which the Rawlsian model fails to see how the political sphere itself is contested, and argues that this demonstrates a need to make the ‘real politics’ of negotiation and compromise central if the public sphere is not to be delegitimised. Bellamy offers a similar analysis of two other seemingly contrasting theorists, Hayek and Walzer, in chapters 1 and 3 respectively.
- Charles W. Mills, ‘“Ideal Theory” as Ideology’, Hypatia vol. 20, no. 3 (2005)
Mills argues that various abstractions and idealisations employed by Rawls and others in their ‘ideal theorising’ are not innocent; on the contrary, they are ideological, in the sense that they reflect dominant groups' privilege and serve to perpetuate it at the expense of the oppressed, whose oppression-relevant characteristics are ignored as a result of the abstractions and idealisations.
- William A. Galston, ‘Realism in political theory’, European Journal of Political Theory, vol. 9, no. 4 (2010)
Galston surveys the various strands of realist critique of ideal theorising, identifying a focus on avoiding evils, confining one's ends to the feasible, and a conception of the political as involving ineliminable conflict as the basic elements. He endorses much of the realist critique, but highlights several ways in which it is, he thinks, nevertheless lacking.
- Alice Baderin, ‘Two forms of realism in political theory’, European Journal of Political Theory vol. 13, no. 2 (2014)
Baderin distinguishes two strands in realist critiques: the “detachment” strand, which argues that political philosophy is too abstract and infeasible, and the “displacement” strand, which argues that political philosophy threatens or disregards real politics. She analyses and identifies tensions between the two strands.
- Simon Hope, ‘Political Philosophy as Practical Philosophy: A Response to “Political Realism”’, The Journal of Political Philosophy vol. 28, no. 4 (2020)
Hope argues that political realists tend to characterise politics too narrowly and in too theoretical (as opposed to practical) a way by what should be realist lights themselves. He goes on to suggest, in Kantian spirit, that once realists take the appropriate practical perspective on politics, the source of the normativity of political judgments will turn out to lie in the nature of practical thought itself.
- Janosch Prinz and Enzo Rossi, ‘Political realism as ideology critique’, Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy vol. 20, no. 3 (2017)
- Matt Sleat (ed.), Politics Recovered: Realist Thought in Theory and Practice (Columbia, 2018)
- Jonathan Leader Maynard, ‘Is There a Distinctively Political Normativity?’, Ethics vol. 128, no. 4 (2018)
Leader Maynard and Worsnip review and reject five realist arguments for the claim that there is a distinctively political type of normativity, a claim that they take to be definitive of political realism.
- Robert Jubb ‘On What a Distinctively Political Normativity Is’, Political Studies Review vol. 17, no. 4 (2019)
Jubb responds to Leader Maynard and Worsnip's arguments before suggesting that realism isn’t best understood in terms claims about types of normativity at all, and offering his own characterisation of realist concerns and method.
- Jonathan Leader Maynard, ‘Political Realism as Methods not Metaethics’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice (2021)
- Edward Hall, ‘Bernard Williams and the Basic Legitimation Demand: A Defence’, Political Studies vol. 63, no. 2 (2015)
Hall gives an account of Williams‘s ’Basic Legitimation Demand’ before defending it from the objections that it ultimately relies on moral claims in just the way that realists say political moralism mistakenly relies on such claims, that it makes legitimacy dependent on unrealistic consensus, and that it is idealistic in its conception of the constitutive conditions of politics.
Hide further reading ⇑
|